Ethics in Healthcare: Balancing Autonomy, Beneficence, Non-Maleficence, and Justice
Verified
Added on 2023/06/11
|4
|797
|232
AI Summary
This article discusses the ethical principles of healthcare workers, including autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice, and how they apply to a case study involving radiography on a pregnant patient.
Contribute Materials
Your contribution can guide someone’s learning journey. Share your
documents today.
Running head: ETHICS1 Ethics Name Institution
Secure Best Marks with AI Grader
Need help grading? Try our AI Grader for instant feedback on your assignments.
ETHICS2 Ethics It is the ethical duty of the health practitioner to seek the consent of a patient before commencing any procedures. Any patient aged 16 years or above like is the case with Jody has the right to consent or not to any clinical procedure proposed by a health therapist (Young, 2010). The relationship between a doctor and their patient is normally underpinned by a professional duty of care. The four main principles that form the basis of the duty of care of all healthcare workers are non-maleficence, justice, respect for autonomy, and beneficence. These four principles help the practitioners in handling ethical dilemmas and at the same time ensuring that the most important factors are not overlooked. From the provided case study, we are informed that Jody tells the oral health therapist about her pregnancy and further requests the doctor to proceed with the radiography and say nothing about the pregnancy to her mother. This happens despite there being protocols prohibiting the use of radiography on expectant women. The ethical standards of practice demand for non-maleficence. The doctors normally possess a sense of morality that ensures they do not cause harm to the patient or anyone else (Beauchamp, 2016). Proceeding with the radiography on Jody puts her unborn child at a higher risk of being born with defects associated with radiography. It would thus be advisable not to proceed with the procedure and follow the due protocols. Another principle that is an important part of the duty of care is beneficence that advocates for the maximization of benefits and minimization of harms to the patient. This principle underlies all the actions that are carried out by the health practitioner (Beauchamp, 2016). In some instances like Jody’s case, the perspective of the patient regarding what they
ETHICS3 deem as being their best interest may not be similar to that of the therapist. As a result, the doctor ends up in a situation with conflicts between beneficence, non-maleficence, and autonomy. He, therefore, has to find a balance between these principles. The third principle is known as justice and it focusses on the right thing that should be done in any situation. Anyone has the same rights in the healthcare setting. The fetus also has a right to justice and must thus be protected from any kind of harm that may be induced by any clinical procedure. The other principle is the respect of autonomy that demands that any decision made by the patient must be respected by the doctor (Wolf, Annas & Elias, 2013). Jody’s oral health therapist, therefore, needs to find a balance between autonomy, rights, and the avoidance of harm. As stipulated in the standards of practice, it is the ethical responsibility of the doctor to respect Jody’s autonomy. However, it is important to discuss with the patient regarding all the benefits of not proceeding with the procedure. The aim of this discussion is not to convince but to provide sufficient information so that the patient can then make an informed decision (Andersson et al., 2010). It could be possible that the radiography is not even a significant necessity and could, therefore, be avoided to protect the fetus from unnecessary harm. Andersson et al. (2010), however, adds that if Jody still insists that the radiograph is taken, then the oral health practitioner could proceed but document that all the risks and benefits of the clinical procedure had been explained to the client.
ETHICS4 References Andersson, G. B., Chapman, J. R., Dekutoski, M. B., Dettori, J., Fehlings, M. G., Fourney, D. R., ... & Weinstein, J. N. (2010). Do no harm: the balance of “beneficence” and “non- maleficence”. Wolf, S. M., Annas, G. J., & Elias, S. (2013). Patient autonomy and incidental findings in clinical genomics.Science,340(6136), 1049-1050. Beauchamp, T. L. (2016). Principlism in Bioethics. InBioethical Decision Making and Argumentation(pp. 1-16). Springer, Cham. Young, R. (2010).Informed consent and patient autonomy(pp. 530-540). Wiley‐Blackwell.